Popular Culture Review Vol. 18, No. 2, Summer 2007 | Page 27

Thinking Things Through 23 self-defeating, since (as Charles Sanders Peirce argued, long ago) the very condition for uttering or expressing it makes it impossible—namely, the words we use to announce or propose it. As Bertrand Russell wrote to an American correspondent who solicited his views on that subject, it’s so nice to meet another solipsist—we must get together more often. If Cartesianism (and its variants) is a contradiction in terms, then communitarianism is the self-evident truth we have so long sought but evaded, thanks to our idolatry of (rugged) individualism (again, attacked by Peirce throughout his long and lonely intellectual career, from 1871 until his death in 1914.^ For Steeves, individuality is relative, not absolute: it applies to cells as well as (to) species (136), and it is never an unqualified essence. As Isaiah Berlin put it in one of his inimitable conversations that I was privileged to overhear [in 1969], “pigs search for tmffles, so naturally they divide the world into truffles and non-truffles.” Likewise, the notion of an individual is a tool, handy for some things, but not others. There is no all purpose tool or all-embracing idea; the quest for such omniscience or reductive omnipotence is both misguided and dangerous. Aristotle held that individuals are always members of classes and thus by definition unknowable; whereas, for William of Occam, Willard van Onnan Quine, and the redoubtable John Wayne, they’re all that is. These extremes betoken the fanaticism that begets them: all or nothing usually means nothing. Steeves takes a moderate position on what Duns Scotus would call haeccity (thisness); he’s no zealot. For him, individuals are neither indispensable nor insidious. Instead, they are useful, fruitful, heuristic concepts or ideals, but only up to a certain point—and beyond that, pointless if not downright pernicious. Yet it takes an individual of Steeves’s caliber to resist and reject entrenched views, and spurn conventional wisdom. If character is destiny, then Steeves has plenty, and is not lacking in the very uniqueness that his opponents reify, or deify. That in turn suggests another admirable quality of Steeves’s book, one we also find in DuBois, and a handful of other synoptic thinkers who grace the annals. Hardly anyone in our country dares to do big picture thinking, theoria in the best sense; even Richard Rorty, who comes the closest, has spent most of his career explaining why theoria is impossible—or as dead as God has been since Pascal, Nietzsche, Hume, Kant, positivism, and Russian anarchists buried him. One either masters one’s problems, or one is mastered by them. Likewise, we represent our times, yet as one great writer saluted another,^^ in rare but compelling cases, they represent us (the age of Newton, the era of Einstein, the minutes of Warhol). Steeves has the right to represent us—and that’s no eulogy. But it does commemorate what he has taken from the stream of thought. He has anticipated our needs, then met them, so we can see who we are in his eyes— and the reflection of our own. This is I/Thou thinking at its finest, and an antidote to the nihilism and emptiness of the age of New Age despair. His book is an epitome and microcosm of human experience, and of his own soul. He isn’t just a theorist, but a witness, a judge of human folly, and a seer. That’s a lot of