Popular Culture Review Vol. 13, No. 2, Summer 2002 | Page 17

Back to Bazin 13 they do not represent qualities unique to it. On the assumption that the possession of qualitative specificity is crucial in determining the ontology of a given object or phenomenon,^ one may therefore conclude that the Bazinian theory of the photographic image - unfashionable as it may seem^ - can still contribute productive insights into the nature of cinema, in the era of computerization perhaps more than ever.^ If, as Bazin has argued, the photographic image works to embalm selected fragments of a profilmic existence, then one could make the claim that the presence of a certain lived reality imprints upon the image its own sohd substance in the form of what Gilles Deleuze terms a mnemosign. The external referent acquires a kind of secondary presence which enables it to transcend and outlive its own impermanence. As Dudley Andrew has remarked, “We accept or even venerate these [photographs] not because they look like the originals, but because their origin stems from direct contact with the objects they call up” (In Lehman 78). With the prevalence of digitized film imagery, this relation between origin and its trace collapses, and results in images without re ferents.^ Hence, what needs to be resolved is the substantial status of this new computerized image, with respect to both ontology on the one hand, and aesthetic and ethical implications on the other. What is at stake, then, in the passage from photography to computer animation is the conservational value of film; the photograph as a record not of the ‘real’ but of a certain presence located at the interstice between fiction and reality. For Bazin, the principal purpose of the filmic is commemorative. He writes that “no one beheves any longer in the ontological identity of model and image, but all are agreed that the image helps us to remember the subject and to preserve him from a second spiritual death” (10). In effect, such an emphasis on the nmemonic function of photography suggests that, teleologically, film is fundamentally concerned with what one could call an ethics of mourning. As Matthews has pointed out, Bazin champions this view with an unflinching moral urgency. According to Bazin, Matthews says, film has a special obligation “to document the world before attempting to interpret or criticize it” (23). It appears that what Bazin intends with his reflections on the ethical basis of filmic preservation is nothing less than to divest memory of its subjective nesting. If not for the invention of photography, his argument goes, this would of course have been impossible (many would indubitably still maintain that this is so). In what is arguably one of the seminal passages in the history of film theory, Bazin consolidates his deliberation: The aesthetic qualities of photography are to be sought in its power to lay bare the realities. It is not for me to separate off, in the complex fabric of the objective world, here a reflection on a damp sidewalk, there the gesture of a child. Only the impassive lens, stripping its object of all